Compare commits
2 commits
6936663173
...
a8c758c5f0
Author | SHA1 | Date | |
---|---|---|---|
a8c758c5f0 | |||
4fc85f8473 |
4 changed files with 238 additions and 0 deletions
40
inputs/lecture_10.tex
Normal file
40
inputs/lecture_10.tex
Normal file
|
@ -0,0 +1,40 @@
|
|||
\lecture{10}{}{} % Mirko
|
||||
|
||||
Applications of induction and recursion:
|
||||
\begin{fact}
|
||||
For every set $x$ there is a transitive set $t$
|
||||
such that $x \in t$.
|
||||
\end{fact}
|
||||
\begin{proof}
|
||||
Take $R = \in $.
|
||||
We want a function $F$ with domain $\omega$
|
||||
such that $F(0) = \{x\}$
|
||||
and $F(n+1) = \bigcup F(n)$.
|
||||
Once we have such a function,
|
||||
$\{x\} \cup \bigcup \ran(F)$
|
||||
is a set as desired.
|
||||
|
||||
\todo{insert formal application of recursion theorem}
|
||||
\end{proof}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{notation}
|
||||
Let $\OR$ denote the class of all ordinals
|
||||
and $V$ the class of all sets.
|
||||
\end{notation}
|
||||
\begin{lemma}
|
||||
There is a function $F\colon \OR \to V$
|
||||
such that $F(\alpha) = \bigcup \{\cP(F(\beta)): \beta < \alpha\}$.
|
||||
\end{lemma}
|
||||
\begin{proof}
|
||||
\todo{TODO}
|
||||
\end{proof}
|
||||
\begin{notation}
|
||||
Usually, one write $V_\alpha$ for $F(\alpha)$.
|
||||
They are called the \vocab{rank initial segments} of $V$.
|
||||
\end{notation}
|
||||
\begin{lemma}
|
||||
If $x$ is any set, then there is some $\alpha \in \OR$
|
||||
such that $x \in V_\alpha$,
|
||||
i.e.~$V = \bigcup \{V_{\alpha} : \alpha \in \OR\}$.
|
||||
\end{lemma}
|
||||
|
195
inputs/lecture_11.tex
Normal file
195
inputs/lecture_11.tex
Normal file
|
@ -0,0 +1,195 @@
|
|||
\lecture{11}{2023-11-23}{Cardinals}
|
||||
|
||||
\subsection{Cardinals}
|
||||
|
||||
Consequence of the Mostowski collapse:
|
||||
|
||||
If $<$ is a well-order on a set $a$
|
||||
then there is some transitive $b$
|
||||
with $(b, \in\defon{b}) \cong (a, <)$.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}
|
||||
Let $a$ be any set.
|
||||
The \vocab{cardinality} of $a$
|
||||
denoted by $\overline{\overline{a}}$, $|a|$ or $\card(a)$,
|
||||
is the smallest ordinal $\alpha$
|
||||
such that there is some bijection $f\colon \alpha \to a$.
|
||||
|
||||
An ordinal $\alpha$ is called a \vocab{cardinal},
|
||||
iff there is some set $a$ with $|a| = \alpha$
|
||||
(equivalently, $|\alpha| = \alpha$).
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
We often write $\kappa, \lambda, \ldots$ for cardinals.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{lemma}
|
||||
For every cardinal $\kappa$,
|
||||
there is come cardinal $\lambda > \kappa$.
|
||||
\end{lemma}
|
||||
\begin{proof}
|
||||
Consider the powerset of $\kappa$.
|
||||
We know that there is no surjection $\kappa \twoheadrightarrow \cP(\kappa)$.
|
||||
Hence $\kappa < |2^{\kappa}|$.
|
||||
\end{proof}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}
|
||||
For each cardinal $\kappa$,
|
||||
$\kappa^+$ denotes the least cardinal $\lambda > \kappa$.
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
\begin{warning}
|
||||
This has nothing to do with the ordinal successor of $\kappa$.
|
||||
\end{warning}
|
||||
\begin{lemma}
|
||||
Let $X$ be any set of cardinals.
|
||||
Then $\sup X$ is a cardinal.
|
||||
\end{lemma}
|
||||
\begin{proof}
|
||||
If there is some $\kappa \in X$ with $\lambda \le \kappa$
|
||||
for all $\lambda \in X$,
|
||||
then $\kappa = \sup(X)$ is a cardinal.
|
||||
|
||||
Let us now assume that for all $\kappa \in X$
|
||||
there is some $\lambda \in X$
|
||||
with $\lambda > \kappa$.
|
||||
Suppose that $\sup(X)$ is no a cardinal
|
||||
and write $\mu = |\sup(X)|$.
|
||||
Then $\mu \in \sup(X)$,
|
||||
since $\sup(X)$ is an ordinal.
|
||||
However $\sup(X)$ is the least ordinal
|
||||
larger than all $\alpha \in X$,
|
||||
so there is $\lambda \in X$
|
||||
with $\lambda > \mu$.
|
||||
However, there exists $\mu \twoheadrightarrow \sup(X)$,
|
||||
hence also $\mu \twoheadrightarrow \lambda$
|
||||
(which is in contradiction to $\lambda$ being a cardinal).
|
||||
\end{proof}
|
||||
We may now use the recursion theorem
|
||||
to define a sequence $\langle \aleph_\alpha : \alpha \in \OR \rangle$
|
||||
with the following properties:
|
||||
\begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl}
|
||||
\aleph_0 &=& \omega,\\
|
||||
\aleph_{\alpha+1} &=& (\aleph_\alpha)^+,\\
|
||||
\aleph_{\lambda} &=& \sup \{\aleph_\alpha : \alpha < \lambda\}.
|
||||
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
||||
Each $\aleph_\alpha$ is a cardinal.
|
||||
Also, a trivial induction show that $\alpha \le \aleph_\alpha$.
|
||||
In particular $|\alpha| \le \aleph_{\alpha}$.
|
||||
Therefore the $\aleph_\alpha$ are all the infinite cardinals:
|
||||
If $a$ is any infinite set, then $|a| \le \aleph_{|a|}$,
|
||||
so $|a| = \aleph_\beta$ for some $\beta \le |\alpha|$.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{notation}
|
||||
Sometimes we write $\omega_\alpha$ for $\aleph_\alpha$
|
||||
(when viewing it as an ordinal).
|
||||
\end{notation}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{notation}
|
||||
Let ${}^a b \coloneqq \{f : f \text{ is a function}, \dom(f) = \alpha, \ran(f) \subseteq b\}$.
|
||||
\end{notation}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}[Cardinal arithmetic]
|
||||
Let $\kappa$, $\lambda$ be cardinals.
|
||||
Define
|
||||
\begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl}
|
||||
\kappa + \lambda &\coloneqq & |\{0\} \times \kappa \cup \{1\} \times \lambda|,\\
|
||||
\kappa \cdot \lambda &\coloneqq & |\kappa \times \lambda|,\\
|
||||
\kappa^{\lambda} &\coloneqq & |{}^{\lambda}\kappa|.
|
||||
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
\begin{warning}
|
||||
This is very different from ordinal arithmetic!
|
||||
\end{warning}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{theorem}[Hessenberg]
|
||||
\label{thm:hessenberg}
|
||||
For all $\alpha$ we have
|
||||
\[
|
||||
\aleph_\alpha \cdot \aleph_\alpha = \aleph_\alpha.
|
||||
\]
|
||||
|
||||
\end{theorem}
|
||||
\begin{corollary}
|
||||
For all $\alpha, \beta$ it is
|
||||
\[
|
||||
\aleph_\alpha + \aleph_\beta = \aleph_\alpha \cdot \aleph_\beta = \max \{\aleph_\alpha, \aleph_\beta\}.
|
||||
\]
|
||||
\end{corollary}
|
||||
\begin{proof}
|
||||
Wlog.~$\alpha \le \beta$.
|
||||
Trivially $\aleph_\alpha \le \aleph_\beta$.
|
||||
It is also clear that
|
||||
\[
|
||||
\aleph_{\beta} \le \aleph_\alpha + \aleph_{\beta} \le \aleph_\alpha \cdot \aleph_\beta \le \aleph_\beta \cdot \aleph_\beta = \aleph_\beta.
|
||||
\]
|
||||
\end{proof}
|
||||
\begin{refproof}{thm:hessenberg}
|
||||
Define a well-order $<^\ast$ on $\OR \times \OR$ by setting
|
||||
\[
|
||||
(\alpha,\beta) <^\ast (\gamma,\delta)
|
||||
\]
|
||||
iff
|
||||
\begin{itemize}
|
||||
\item $\max(\alpha,\beta) < \max(\gamma,\delta)$ or
|
||||
\item $\max(\alpha,\beta) = \max(\gamma,\delta)$ and $\alpha < \gamma$ or
|
||||
\item $\max(\alpha,\beta) = \max(\gamma,\delta)$ and $\alpha = \gamma$ and $\beta < \delta$.
|
||||
\end{itemize}
|
||||
|
||||
It is clear that this is a well-order.
|
||||
|
||||
There is an isomorphism
|
||||
\[
|
||||
(\OR, <) \cong^{\Gamma^{-1}} (\OR \times \OR, <^\ast).
|
||||
\]
|
||||
$\Gamma$ is called the \vocab{Gödel pairing function}.
|
||||
\begin{claim}
|
||||
For all $\alpha$ it is
|
||||
$\ran(\Gamma\defon{\aleph_\alpha \times \aleph_\alpha})) = \aleph_\alpha$,
|
||||
i.e.
|
||||
\[
|
||||
\aleph_\alpha = \{\xi: \exists \eta, \eta' < \aleph_\alpha.~\xi = \Gamma((\eta,\eta'))\}.
|
||||
\]
|
||||
\end{claim}
|
||||
\begin{subproof}
|
||||
We use induction of $\alpha$.
|
||||
The claim is trivial for $\alpha = 0$.
|
||||
Now let $\alpha > 0$ and suppose the claim
|
||||
to be true for all $\beta < \alpha$.
|
||||
It is easy to see that
|
||||
\[
|
||||
\ran(\Gamma\defon{\aleph_\alpha \times \aleph_\alpha}) \supseteq \aleph_\alpha,
|
||||
\]
|
||||
as otherwise $\Gamma\defon{\aleph_\alpha \times \alepha_\alpha}: \alepha_{\alpha} \times \alepha_\alpha \to \eta$
|
||||
would be a bijection for some $\eta < \alepha_\alpha$,
|
||||
but $\alepha_\alpha$ is a cardinal.
|
||||
|
||||
Suppose that $\ran(\Gamma\defon{\aleph_\alpha \times \alepha_\alpha}) \supsetneq \aleph_\alpha$.
|
||||
Then there exist $\eta, \eta' < \aleph_\alpha$ with
|
||||
\[
|
||||
\Gamma((\eta, \eta')) = \alepha_\alpha.
|
||||
\]
|
||||
|
||||
So $\Gamma\defon{\{(\gamma,\delta) : (\gamma,\delta) <^\ast (\eta, \eta'\}}$
|
||||
is bijective onto $\alepha_\alpha$.
|
||||
If $(\gamma,\delta) <^\ast (\eta, \eta')$,
|
||||
then $\max \{\gamma,\delta\} \le \max \{\eta, \eta'\}$.
|
||||
Say $\eta \le \eta' < \alepha_\alpha$
|
||||
and let $\aleph_\alpha = |\eta'|$.
|
||||
There is a surjection
|
||||
\[f\colon \underbrace{(\eta +1)}_{ \le \aleph_\beta} \times \underbrace{(\eta' + 1)}_{\sim \aleph_\beta} \twoheadrightarrow \aleph_\alpha.\]
|
||||
|
||||
This gives rise to a surjection $f^\ast \colon \aleph_\beta \times \aleph_\beta \to \aleph_\alpha$.
|
||||
The inductive hypothesis then produces a surjection
|
||||
$f^\ast\colon \aleph_\beta \to \aleph_\alpha \lightning$.
|
||||
\end{subproof}
|
||||
\end{refproof}
|
||||
However, exponentiation of cardinals is far from trivial:
|
||||
\begin{observe}
|
||||
$2^{\kappa} = |\cP(\kappa)|$,
|
||||
since ${}^{\kappa} \{0,1\} \leftrightarrow\cP(\kappa)$.
|
||||
|
||||
Hence by Cantor $2^{\kappa}\ge \kappa^+$.
|
||||
\end{observe}
|
||||
This is basically all we can say.
|
||||
|
||||
The \vocab{continuum hypothesis} states that $2^{\aleph_0} = \aleph_1$.
|
||||
|
|
@ -129,6 +129,7 @@
|
|||
\DeclareSimpleMathOperator{CH}
|
||||
\DeclareSimpleMathOperator{DC}
|
||||
\DeclareSimpleMathOperator{Ord}
|
||||
\DeclareSimpleMathOperator{OR} % Ordinals
|
||||
\DeclareSimpleMathOperator{trcl}
|
||||
\DeclareSimpleMathOperator{tcl}
|
||||
\newcommand{\concat}{{}^\frown}
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -33,6 +33,8 @@
|
|||
\input{inputs/lecture_07}
|
||||
\input{inputs/lecture_08}
|
||||
\input{inputs/lecture_09}
|
||||
% TODO \input{inputs/lecture_10}
|
||||
\input{inputs/lecture_11}
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
\cleardoublepage
|
||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue