This commit is contained in:
parent
67a851748e
commit
c03a62f638
6 changed files with 159 additions and 109 deletions
|
@ -103,7 +103,9 @@
|
||||||
Let $X$ be a completely metrizable space.
|
Let $X$ be a completely metrizable space.
|
||||||
Then every comeager set of $X$ is dense in $X$.
|
Then every comeager set of $X$ is dense in $X$.
|
||||||
\end{theorem}
|
\end{theorem}
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
\todo{Proof (copy from some other lecture)}
|
\todo{Proof (copy from some other lecture)}
|
||||||
|
}{Not proved in the lecture.}
|
||||||
\begin{theoremdef}
|
\begin{theoremdef}
|
||||||
Let $X$ be a topological space.
|
Let $X$ be a topological space.
|
||||||
The following are equivalent:
|
The following are equivalent:
|
||||||
|
@ -118,7 +120,21 @@
|
||||||
\footnote{cf.~\yaref{s5e1}}
|
\footnote{cf.~\yaref{s5e1}}
|
||||||
\end{theoremdef}
|
\end{theoremdef}
|
||||||
\begin{proof}
|
\begin{proof}
|
||||||
\todo{Proof (short)}
|
(i) $\implies$ (ii)
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
|
Consider a comeager set $A$.
|
||||||
|
Let $U\neq \emptyset$ be any open set. Since $U$ is
|
||||||
|
non-meager, we have $A \cap U \neq \emptyset$.
|
||||||
|
}{The intersection of a comeager and a non-meager set is nonempty.}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
(ii) $\implies$ (iii)
|
||||||
|
The complement of an open dense set is nwd.
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
|
Hence the intersection of countable
|
||||||
|
many open dense sets is comeager.
|
||||||
|
}{}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
(iii) $\implies$ (i)
|
(iii) $\implies$ (i)
|
||||||
Let us first show that $X$ is non-meager.
|
Let us first show that $X$ is non-meager.
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -77,7 +77,7 @@
|
||||||
sets that are not clopen)}{}.
|
sets that are not clopen)}{}.
|
||||||
\end{example}
|
\end{example}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\subsection{Turning Borels Sets into Clopens}
|
\subsection{Turning Borel Sets into Clopens}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{theorem}%
|
\begin{theorem}%
|
||||||
\gist{%
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
|
@ -109,6 +109,7 @@
|
||||||
into $B$.
|
into $B$.
|
||||||
\end{corollary}
|
\end{corollary}
|
||||||
\begin{proof}
|
\begin{proof}
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
Pick $\cT_B \supset \cT$
|
Pick $\cT_B \supset \cT$
|
||||||
such that $(X, \cT_B)$ is Polish,
|
such that $(X, \cT_B)$ is Polish,
|
||||||
$B$ is clopen in $\cT_B$ and
|
$B$ is clopen in $\cT_B$ and
|
||||||
|
@ -121,10 +122,17 @@
|
||||||
Consider $f\colon 2^{\omega} \to B \subseteq (X, \cT)$.
|
Consider $f\colon 2^{\omega} \to B \subseteq (X, \cT)$.
|
||||||
This is still continuous as $\cT \subseteq \cT_B$.
|
This is still continuous as $\cT \subseteq \cT_B$.
|
||||||
Since $2^{\omega}$ is compact, $f$ is an embedding.
|
Since $2^{\omega}$ is compact, $f$ is an embedding.
|
||||||
%\todo{Think about this}
|
}{%
|
||||||
|
Clopenize $B$.
|
||||||
|
We can embed $2^{ \omega}$ into Polish spaces.
|
||||||
|
Clopenization makes the topology finer,
|
||||||
|
so this is still continuous wrt.~the original topology.
|
||||||
|
$2^{\omega}$ is compact, so this is an embedding.
|
||||||
|
}
|
||||||
\end{proof}
|
\end{proof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{refproof}{thm:clopenize}
|
\begin{refproof}{thm:clopenize}
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
We show that
|
We show that
|
||||||
\begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl}
|
\begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl}
|
||||||
A \coloneqq \{B \subseteq \cB(X, \cT)&:\exists & \cT_B \supseteq \cT .\\
|
A \coloneqq \{B \subseteq \cB(X, \cT)&:\exists & \cT_B \supseteq \cT .\\
|
||||||
|
@ -134,18 +142,26 @@
|
||||||
\}
|
\}
|
||||||
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
||||||
is equal to the set of Borel sets.
|
is equal to the set of Borel sets.
|
||||||
|
}{%
|
||||||
The proof rests on two lemmata:
|
Let $A$ be the set of clopenizable sets.
|
||||||
|
We show that $A = \cB(X)$.
|
||||||
|
}
|
||||||
|
\gist{The proof rests on two lemmata:}{}
|
||||||
\begin{lemma}
|
\begin{lemma}
|
||||||
\label{thm:clopenize:l1}
|
\label{thm:clopenize:l1}
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
Let $(X,\cT)$ be a Polish space.
|
Let $(X,\cT)$ be a Polish space.
|
||||||
Then for any $F \overset{\text{closed}}{\subseteq} X$ (wrt. $\cT$)
|
Then for any $F \overset{\text{closed}}{\subseteq} X$ (wrt. $\cT$)
|
||||||
there is $\cT_F \supseteq \cT$
|
there is $\cT_F \supseteq \cT$
|
||||||
such that $\cT_F$ is Polish,
|
such that $\cT_F$ is Polish,
|
||||||
$\cB(\cT) = \cB(\cT_F)$
|
$\cB(\cT) = \cB(\cT_F)$
|
||||||
and $F$ is clopen in $\cT_F$.
|
and $F$ is clopen in $\cT_F$.
|
||||||
|
}{%
|
||||||
|
Closed sets can be clopenized.
|
||||||
|
}
|
||||||
\end{lemma}
|
\end{lemma}
|
||||||
\begin{proof}
|
\begin{proof}
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
Consider $(F, \cT\defon{F})$ and $(X \setminus F, \cT\defon{X \setminus F})$.
|
Consider $(F, \cT\defon{F})$ and $(X \setminus F, \cT\defon{X \setminus F})$.
|
||||||
Both are Polish spaces.
|
Both are Polish spaces.
|
||||||
Take the coproduct%
|
Take the coproduct%
|
||||||
|
@ -154,10 +170,13 @@
|
||||||
This space is Polish,
|
This space is Polish,
|
||||||
and the topology is generated by $\cT \cup \{F\}$,
|
and the topology is generated by $\cT \cup \{F\}$,
|
||||||
hence we do not get any new Borel sets.
|
hence we do not get any new Borel sets.
|
||||||
|
}{Consider $(F, \cT\defon{F}) \oplus (X \setminus F, \cT\defon{X \setminus F})$.}
|
||||||
\end{proof}
|
\end{proof}
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
So all closed sets are in $A$.
|
So all closed sets are in $A$.
|
||||||
Furthermore $A$ is closed under complements,
|
Furthermore $A$ is closed under complements,
|
||||||
since complements of clopen sets are clopen.
|
since complements of clopen sets are clopen.
|
||||||
|
}{So $\Sigma^0_1(X), \Pi^0_1(X) \subseteq A$.}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{lemma}
|
\begin{lemma}
|
||||||
\label{thm:clopenize:l2}
|
\label{thm:clopenize:l2}
|
||||||
|
@ -170,11 +189,11 @@
|
||||||
is Polish
|
is Polish
|
||||||
and $\cB(\cT_\infty) = \cB(T)$.
|
and $\cB(\cT_\infty) = \cB(T)$.
|
||||||
\end{lemma}
|
\end{lemma}
|
||||||
\begin{proof}
|
\begin{refproof}{thm:clopenize:l2}
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
We have that $\cT_\infty$ is the smallest
|
We have that $\cT_\infty$ is the smallest
|
||||||
topology containing all $\cT_n$.
|
topology containing all $\cT_n$.
|
||||||
To get $\cT_\infty$
|
To get $\cT_\infty$ consider
|
||||||
consider
|
|
||||||
\[
|
\[
|
||||||
\cF \coloneqq \{A_1 \cap A_2 \cap \ldots \cap A_n : A_i \in \cT_i\}.
|
\cF \coloneqq \{A_1 \cap A_2 \cap \ldots \cap A_n : A_i \in \cT_i\}.
|
||||||
\]
|
\]
|
||||||
|
@ -186,6 +205,7 @@
|
||||||
since we may assume that the $A_1, \ldots, A_n$ in the
|
since we may assume that the $A_1, \ldots, A_n$ in the
|
||||||
definition of $\cF$ belong to
|
definition of $\cF$ belong to
|
||||||
a countable basis of the respective $\cT_n$).
|
a countable basis of the respective $\cT_n$).
|
||||||
|
}{}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
% Proof was finished in lecture 8
|
% Proof was finished in lecture 8
|
||||||
Let $Y = \prod_{n \in \N} (X, \cT_n)$.
|
Let $Y = \prod_{n \in \N} (X, \cT_n)$.
|
||||||
|
@ -195,6 +215,7 @@
|
||||||
\begin{claim}
|
\begin{claim}
|
||||||
$\delta$ is a homeomorphism.
|
$\delta$ is a homeomorphism.
|
||||||
\end{claim}
|
\end{claim}
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
\begin{subproof}
|
\begin{subproof}
|
||||||
Clearly $\delta$ is a bijection.
|
Clearly $\delta$ is a bijection.
|
||||||
We need to show that it is continuous and open.
|
We need to show that it is continuous and open.
|
||||||
|
@ -219,21 +240,26 @@
|
||||||
\delta(V) = D \cap (X \times X \times \ldots \times U_{n_1} \times \ldots \times U_{n_2} \times \ldots \times U_{n_u} \times X \times \ldots) \overset{\text{open}}{\subseteq} D.
|
\delta(V) = D \cap (X \times X \times \ldots \times U_{n_1} \times \ldots \times U_{n_2} \times \ldots \times U_{n_u} \times X \times \ldots) \overset{\text{open}}{\subseteq} D.
|
||||||
\]
|
\]
|
||||||
\end{subproof}
|
\end{subproof}
|
||||||
|
}{}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
This will finish the proof since
|
\begin{claim}
|
||||||
\[
|
$D = \{(x,x,\ldots) \in Y : x \in X\} \overset{\text{closed}}{\subseteq} Y.$
|
||||||
D = \{(x,x,\ldots) \in Y : x \in X\} \overset{\text{closed}}{\subseteq} Y
|
\end{claim}
|
||||||
\]
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
Why? Let $(x_n) \in Y \setminus D$.
|
\begin{subproof}
|
||||||
|
Let $(x_n) \in Y \setminus D$.
|
||||||
Then there are $i < j$ such that $x_i \neq x_j$.
|
Then there are $i < j$ such that $x_i \neq x_j$.
|
||||||
Take disjoint open $x_i \in U$, $x_j \in V$.
|
Take disjoint open $x_i \in U$, $x_j \in V$.
|
||||||
Then
|
Then
|
||||||
\[(x_n) \in X \times X \times \ldots \times U \times \ldots \times X \times \ldots \times V \times X \times \ldots\]
|
\[(x_n) \in X \times X \times \ldots \times U \times \ldots \times X \times \ldots \times V \times X \times \ldots\]
|
||||||
is open in $Y\setminus D$.
|
is open in $Y\setminus D$.
|
||||||
Hence $Y \setminus D$ is open, thus $D$ is closed.
|
Hence $Y \setminus D$ is open, thus $D$ is closed.
|
||||||
|
\end{subproof}
|
||||||
It follows that $D$ is Polish.
|
It follows that $D$ is Polish.
|
||||||
\end{proof}
|
}{}
|
||||||
|
\end{refproof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
We need to show that $A$ is closed under countable unions.
|
We need to show that $A$ is closed under countable unions.
|
||||||
By \yaref{thm:clopenize:l2} there exists a topology
|
By \yaref{thm:clopenize:l2} there exists a topology
|
||||||
$\cT_\infty$ such that $A = \bigcup_{n < \omega} A_n$ is open in $\cT_\infty$
|
$\cT_\infty$ such that $A = \bigcup_{n < \omega} A_n$ is open in $\cT_\infty$
|
||||||
|
@ -243,4 +269,5 @@
|
||||||
$(X, \cT_\infty')$ is Polish,
|
$(X, \cT_\infty')$ is Polish,
|
||||||
$\cB(\cT_\infty') = \cB(\cT)$
|
$\cB(\cT_\infty') = \cB(\cT)$
|
||||||
and $A $ is clopen in $\cT_{\infty}'$.
|
and $A $ is clopen in $\cT_{\infty}'$.
|
||||||
|
}{}
|
||||||
\end{refproof}
|
\end{refproof}
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -1,8 +1,9 @@
|
||||||
\lecture{08}{2023-11-10}{}\footnote{%
|
\lecture{08}{2023-11-10}{}%
|
||||||
|
\gist{\footnote{%
|
||||||
In the beginning of the lecture, we finished
|
In the beginning of the lecture, we finished
|
||||||
the proof of \yaref{thm:clopenize:l2}.
|
the proof of \yaref{thm:clopenize:l2}.
|
||||||
This has been moved to the notes on lecture 7.%
|
This has been moved to the notes on lecture 7.%
|
||||||
}
|
}}{}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\subsection{Parametrizations}
|
\subsection{Parametrizations}
|
||||||
%\todo{choose better title}
|
%\todo{choose better title}
|
||||||
|
@ -22,13 +23,14 @@ where $X$ is a metrizable, usually second countable space.
|
||||||
\item $\{U_y : y \in Y\} = \Gamma(X)$.
|
\item $\{U_y : y \in Y\} = \Gamma(X)$.
|
||||||
\end{itemize}
|
\end{itemize}
|
||||||
\end{definition}
|
\end{definition}
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
\begin{example}
|
\begin{example}
|
||||||
Let $X = \omega^\omega$, $Y = 2^{\omega}$
|
Let $X = \omega^\omega$, $Y = 2^{\omega}$
|
||||||
and consider $\Gamma = \Sigma^0_{\omega+5}(\omega^\omega)$.
|
and consider $\Gamma = \Sigma^0_{\omega+5}(\omega^\omega)$.
|
||||||
We will show that there is a $2^{\omega}$-universal
|
We will show that there is a $2^{\omega}$-universal
|
||||||
set for $\Gamma$.
|
set for $\Gamma$.
|
||||||
\end{example}
|
\end{example}
|
||||||
|
}{}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{theorem}
|
\begin{theorem}
|
||||||
\label{thm:cantoruniversal}
|
\label{thm:cantoruniversal}
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -99,9 +99,10 @@
|
||||||
(continuous wrt.~to the topology of $X$)
|
(continuous wrt.~to the topology of $X$)
|
||||||
On the other hand
|
On the other hand
|
||||||
\[
|
\[
|
||||||
X \hookrightarrow\cN \overset{\text{continuous embedding}}{\hookrightarrow}\cC
|
X \hookrightarrow\cN \overset{\text{continuous embedding\footnotemark}}{\hookrightarrow}\cC
|
||||||
\]
|
\]
|
||||||
\todo{second inclusion was on a homework sheet}
|
\footnotetext{cf.~\yaref{s2e4}}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
For the first inclusion,
|
For the first inclusion,
|
||||||
recall that there is a continuous bijection $b\colon D \to X$,
|
recall that there is a continuous bijection $b\colon D \to X$,
|
||||||
where $D \overset{\text{closed}}{\subseteq} \cN$.
|
where $D \overset{\text{closed}}{\subseteq} \cN$.
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -79,8 +79,6 @@ with $(f^{-1}(\{1\}), <)$.
|
||||||
}{easy}
|
}{easy}
|
||||||
\end{proof}
|
\end{proof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
% TODO ANKI-MARKER
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{theorem}[Lusin-Sierpinski]
|
\begin{theorem}[Lusin-Sierpinski]
|
||||||
The set $\LO \setminus \WO$
|
The set $\LO \setminus \WO$
|
||||||
(resp.~$2^{\Q} \setminus \WO$)
|
(resp.~$2^{\Q} \setminus \WO$)
|
||||||
|
@ -89,19 +87,23 @@ with $(f^{-1}(\{1\}), <)$.
|
||||||
\begin{proof}
|
\begin{proof}
|
||||||
We will find a continuous function
|
We will find a continuous function
|
||||||
$f\colon \Tr \to \LO$ such that
|
$f\colon \Tr \to \LO$ such that
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
\[
|
\[
|
||||||
x \in \WF \iff f(x) \in \WO
|
x \in \WF \iff f(x) \in \WO
|
||||||
\]
|
\]
|
||||||
(equivalently $x \in \IF \iff f(x) \in \LO \setminus \WO$).
|
(equivalently $x \in \IF \iff f(x) \in \LO \setminus \WO$).
|
||||||
This suffices, since $\IF \subseteq \Tr$ is $\Sigma^1_1$-complete
|
This suffices, since $\IF \subseteq \Tr$ is $\Sigma^1_1$-complete
|
||||||
|
}{
|
||||||
|
$f^{-1}(\LO \setminus \WO) = \IF$.
|
||||||
|
This suffices
|
||||||
|
}
|
||||||
(see \yaref{cor:ifs11c}).
|
(see \yaref{cor:ifs11c}).
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Fix a bijection $b\colon \N \to \N^{<\N}$.
|
Fix a bijection $b\colon \N \to \N^{<\N}$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{idea}
|
\begin{idea}
|
||||||
For $T \in \Tr$ consider
|
For $T \in \Tr$ consider
|
||||||
$<_{KB}\defon{T}$
|
$<_{KB}\defon{T}$.
|
||||||
% TODO?
|
|
||||||
\end{idea}
|
\end{idea}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Let $\alpha \in \Tr$.
|
Let $\alpha \in \Tr$.
|
||||||
|
@ -109,7 +111,7 @@ with $(f^{-1}(\{1\}), <)$.
|
||||||
(i.e.~$m \le_{f(\alpha)} n$)
|
(i.e.~$m \le_{f(\alpha)} n$)
|
||||||
iff
|
iff
|
||||||
\begin{itemize}
|
\begin{itemize}
|
||||||
\item $(\alpha(b(m)) = \alpha(b(n)) = 1$
|
\item $\alpha(b(m)) = \alpha(b(n)) = 1$
|
||||||
and $b(m) \le_{KB} b(n)$
|
and $b(m) \le_{KB} b(n)$
|
||||||
(recall that we identified $\Tr$
|
(recall that we identified $\Tr$
|
||||||
with a subset of ${2^{\N}}^{<\N}$),
|
with a subset of ${2^{\N}}^{<\N}$),
|
||||||
|
@ -123,7 +125,7 @@ with $(f^{-1}(\{1\}), <)$.
|
||||||
\end{proof}
|
\end{proof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
% TODO: new section?
|
% TODO: new section?
|
||||||
|
\gist{%
|
||||||
Recall that a \vocab{rank} on a set $C$
|
Recall that a \vocab{rank} on a set $C$
|
||||||
is a map $\phi\colon C \to \Ord$.
|
is a map $\phi\colon C \to \Ord$.
|
||||||
\begin{example}
|
\begin{example}
|
||||||
|
@ -132,6 +134,7 @@ is a map $\phi\colon C \to \Ord$.
|
||||||
x &\longmapsto & \text{the unique $\alpha \in \Ord$ such that $x \cong \alpha$}.
|
x &\longmapsto & \text{the unique $\alpha \in \Ord$ such that $x \cong \alpha$}.
|
||||||
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
||||||
\end{example}
|
\end{example}
|
||||||
|
}{}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{definition}
|
\begin{definition}
|
||||||
A \vocab{prewellordering} $\preceq$
|
A \vocab{prewellordering} $\preceq$
|
||||||
|
@ -141,7 +144,7 @@ is a map $\phi\colon C \to \Ord$.
|
||||||
\item reflexive,
|
\item reflexive,
|
||||||
\item transitive,
|
\item transitive,
|
||||||
\item total (any two $x,y$ are comparable),
|
\item total (any two $x,y$ are comparable),
|
||||||
\item $\prec$ ($x \prec y \iff x \preceq y \land y \not\preceq x$) is well-founded,
|
\item $\prec$ \gist{($x \prec y \iff x \preceq y \land y \not\preceq x$)}{} is well-founded,
|
||||||
in the sense that there are no descending infinite chains.
|
in the sense that there are no descending infinite chains.
|
||||||
\end{itemize}
|
\end{itemize}
|
||||||
\end{definition}
|
\end{definition}
|
||||||
|
@ -149,7 +152,7 @@ is a map $\phi\colon C \to \Ord$.
|
||||||
\begin{itemize}
|
\begin{itemize}
|
||||||
\item A prewellordering may not be a linear order since
|
\item A prewellordering may not be a linear order since
|
||||||
it is not necessarily antisymmetric.
|
it is not necessarily antisymmetric.
|
||||||
\item The linearly ordered wellfounded sets are exactly the wellordered sets.
|
%\item The linearly ordered wellfounded sets are exactly the wellordered sets.
|
||||||
\item Modding out $x \sim y :\iff x \preceq y \land y \preceq x$
|
\item Modding out $x \sim y :\iff x \preceq y \land y \preceq x$
|
||||||
turns a prewellordering into a wellordering.
|
turns a prewellordering into a wellordering.
|
||||||
\end{itemize}
|
\end{itemize}
|
||||||
|
@ -163,11 +166,11 @@ between downwards-closed ranks and prewellorderings:
|
||||||
\phi_{\preceq}&\longmapsfrom& \preceq,
|
\phi_{\preceq}&\longmapsfrom& \preceq,
|
||||||
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
||||||
where $\phi_\preceq(x)$ is defined as
|
where $\phi_\preceq(x)$ is defined as
|
||||||
\begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl}
|
\gist{\begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl}
|
||||||
\phi_{\preceq}(x) &\coloneqq &0 \text{ if $x$ is minimal},\\
|
\phi_{\preceq}(x) &\coloneqq &0 \text{ if $x$ is minimal},\\
|
||||||
\phi_{\preceq}(x) &\coloneqq & \sup \{\phi_{\preceq}(y) + 1 : y \prec x\},
|
\phi_{\preceq}(x) &\coloneqq & \sup \{\phi_{\preceq}(y) + 1 : y \prec x\},
|
||||||
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
||||||
i.e.
|
i.e.}{}
|
||||||
\[
|
\[
|
||||||
\phi_{\preceq}(x) = \otp\left(\faktor{\{y \in C : y \prec x\}}{\sim}\right).
|
\phi_{\preceq}(x) = \otp\left(\faktor{\{y \in C : y \prec x\}}{\sim}\right).
|
||||||
\]
|
\]
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -1,5 +1,6 @@
|
||||||
\lecture{14}{2023-12-01}{}
|
\lecture{14}{2023-12-01}{}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
% TODO ANKI-MARKER
|
||||||
\begin{theorem}[Moschovakis]
|
\begin{theorem}[Moschovakis]
|
||||||
If $C$ is coanalytic,
|
If $C$ is coanalytic,
|
||||||
then there exists a $\Pi^1_1$-rank on $C$.
|
then there exists a $\Pi^1_1$-rank on $C$.
|
||||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue