Merge branch 'main' of https://git.abstractnonsen.se/josia-notes/w23-logic-3
Some checks failed
Build latex and deploy / checkout (push) Failing after 17m41s

This commit is contained in:
Josia Pietsch 2024-01-23 14:29:32 +01:00
commit 09658bbcb5
Signed by: josia
GPG Key ID: E70B571D66986A2D
2 changed files with 179 additions and 0 deletions

178
inputs/lecture_24.tex Normal file
View File

@ -0,0 +1,178 @@
\lecture{24}{2024-01-23}{Combinatorics!}
\subsection{Applications to Combinatorics} % Ramsey Theory}
% TODO Define Ultrafilter
\begin{definition}
An \vocab{ultrafilter} on $\N$ (or any other set)
is a family $\cU \subseteq \cP(\N)$
such that
\begin{enumerate}[(1)]
\item $X \in \cU \land X \subseteq Y \subseteq \N \implies Y \in \cU$.
\item $X,Y \in \cU \implies X \cap Y \in \cU$.
\item $\emptyset \not\in \cU$, $\N \in \cU$.
\item For all $X \subseteq \N$,
we have $X \in \cU \lor \N \setminus X \in \cU$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{definition}
\begin{remark}
\begin{itemize}
\item If $X \cup Y \in \cU$ then $X \in \cU \lor Y$ or $Y \in \cU$:
Consider $((\N \setminus X) \cap (\N \setminus Y) = \N \setminus (X \cup Y)$.
\item Every filter can be extended to an ultrafilter.
(Zorn's lemma)
\end{itemize}
\end{remark}
\begin{definition}
An ultrafilter is called \vocab[Ultrafilter!principal]{principal} or \vocab[Ultrafilter!trivial]{trivial}
if it is of the form
\[
\hat{n} = \{X \subseteq \N : n \in X\}.
\]
\end{definition}
\begin{notation}
Let $\phi(\cdot )$ be a formula, where the argument is a natural number.
Let $\cU$ be an ultrafilter.
We write
\[
(\cU n) ~ \phi(n)
\]
for $\{ n \in \N : \phi(n)\} \in \cU$.
We say that $\phi(n)$ holds for \vocab{$\cU$-almost all} $n$.
\end{notation}
\begin{observe}
Let $\phi(\cdot )$, $\psi(\cdot )$ be formulas.
\begin{enumerate}[(1)]
\item $(\cU n) (\phi(n) \land \psi(m)) \iff (\cU n) \phi(n) \land (\cU n) \psi(n)$.
\item $(\cU n) (\phi(n) \lor \psi(m)) \iff (\cU n) \phi(n) \lor (\cU n) \psi(n)$.
\item $(\cU n) \lnot \phi(n) \iff \lnot (\cU n) \phi(n)$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{observe}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lem:ultrafilterlimit}
Let $X $ be a compact Hausdorff space.
Let $\cU$ be an ultrafilter.
Then for every sequence $(x_n)$ in $X$,
there is a unique $x \in X$,
such that
\[
(\cU_n) (x_n \in G)
\]
for every neighbourhood%
\footnote{$G \subseteq X$ is a neighbourhood iff $x \in \inter G$.}
$G$ of $x$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{notation}
In this case we write $x = \cU-\lim_n x_n$.
\end{notation}
\begin{refproof}{lem:ultrafilterlimit}[sketch]
Whenever we write $X = Y \cup Z$
we have $(\cU n) x_n \in Y$
or $(\cU n) x_n \in Z$.
So we can repeatedly chop the space in two pieces,
one of them contains $\cU$-almost all $x_n$,
Then we restrict to this piece and continue.
For this to work, we need
a finite collection $\cP_n$ of closed sets for every $n$,
such that $\bigcup \cP_n = X$,
$C \in \cP_{n+1} \implies \exists C \subseteq D \in \cP_{n}$
and
$C_1 \supseteq C_2 \supseteq \ldots$, $C_i \in \cP_i $ $\implies | \bigcap_{i} C_i| = 1$.
It is clear that we can do this for metric spaces,
but such partition can be found for compact Hausdorff spaces as well.
\end{refproof}
Let $\beta \N$ be the Čech-Stone compactification of $\N$,
i.e.~the set of all ultrafilters on $\N$
with the topology given by open sets $V_{A} = \{ p \in \beta\N : A \in P\} $
for $A \subseteq \N$.
This is a compact Hausdorff space.\todo{Homework}
We can turn it into a compact semigroup:
Consider $+ \colon \N \times \N \to \N$.
This gives an operation on principal ultrafilters
(we identify $n \in \N$ with the corresponding principal filter).
We want to extend this to all of $\beta\N$.
Fix the first argument to get a function $\N \to \N, n \mapsto k+n$.
For $\cU \in \beta\N$ consider $\cU-\lim_n (k+n)$.
So for a fixed $k \in \N$ we get $k+ \cdot \colon\beta\N \to \beta\N$,
i.e.~$+ \colon \N \times \beta\N \to \beta\N$.
Fixing the second coordinate to be $\cV \in \beta\N$,
we get a function $+\cV \colon \N \to \beta\N$.
For $ \cU \in \beta\N$
consider $\cU-\lim_n n + \cV$.
This gives $+ \colon \beta\N \times \beta\N \to \beta\N$.
% TODO ?
\[
\cU + \cV = \{X \subseteq \N : \{m \colon \{n \colon m+n \in X\} \in \cV \} \in \cU \}.
\]
This is not commutative,
but associative and $a \mapsto a + b$ is continuous
for a fixed $b$.
This is called a left compact topological semigroup.
Let $X$ be a compact Hausdorff space
and let $T \colon X \to X$ be continuous.%
\footnote{Note that this need not be a homeomorphism, i.e.~we only get a $\N$-action
but not a $\Z$-action.}
For any $\cU \in \beta\N$, we define $T^{\cU}$ by
$T^\cU(x) \coloneqq \cU-\lim_n T^n(x)$ for $x \in X$.
For fixed $x$, the map $\cU \mapsto T^{\cU}(x)$ is continuous.
(More generally, for every $f\colon \N \to X$
the extension $\tilde{f}\colon \beta\N \to X$ is continuous).
Note that for fixed $\cU$, the map $x \mapsto T^\cU(x)$
is not necessarily continuous.
\begin{definition}
Let $X$ be a compact Hausdorff space
and $T\colon X\to X$ continuous.
A point $x \in X$ is \vocab{recurrent},
iff for every neighbourhood $G$ of $x$,
infinitely many $n$ satisfy $T^n(x) \in G$.
A point $x \in X$ is \vocab{uniformly recurrent},
if for every neighbourhood $G$ of $x$,
there exists $M \in \N$,
such that
\[
\forall n.~\exists k < M.~ T^{n+k}(x) \in G.
\]
\end{definition}
\begin{fact}
Let $\cU, \cV \in \beta\N$
and $T\colon X \to X$ continuous
for a compact Hausdorff space $X$.
Then $T^{\cU}(T^{\cV}(x)) = T^{\cU + \cV}(x)$.
\end{fact}
\begin{proof}
\begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl}
T^{\cU + \cV}(x) &=& (\cU + \cV)-\lim_k T^k(x)\\
&=& \cU-\lim_m \cV-\lim_n T^{m+n}(x)\\
&\overset{T^m \text{ continuous}}{=}& \cU-\lim_m T^m (\cV-\lim_n T^n(x))\\
&=& T^\cU(T^\cV(x)).
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
\end{proof}
\todo{Homework: Check the details that were omitted during the lecture.}

View File

@ -50,6 +50,7 @@
\input{inputs/lecture_21}
\input{inputs/lecture_22}
\input{inputs/lecture_23}
\input{inputs/lecture_24}
\cleardoublepage