Compare commits

...

3 commits

Author SHA1 Message Date
ab14be172f
some small changes
Some checks failed
Build latex and deploy / checkout (push) Failing after 14m16s
2024-02-16 19:47:21 +01:00
c03b6fc0ef
Merge branch 'master' of https://git.abstractnonsen.se/josia-notes/w23-logic-2 2024-02-16 19:28:29 +01:00
115aba1670
remark on stationary sets, closedness of diagonal intersection 2024-02-16 19:28:21 +01:00
7 changed files with 67 additions and 51 deletions

View file

@ -39,7 +39,6 @@
is not a well-order on a countable set.
Thus $\otp(\faktor{W}{\sim}, <) = \omega_1$.
\todo{move this}
\end{remark}
}{}

View file

@ -150,11 +150,20 @@ We have shown (assuming \AxC to choose contained clubs):
The \vocab{diagonal intersection},
is defined to be
\[
\diagi_{\beta < \alpha} A_{\beta} \coloneqq
\diagi_{\beta < \alpha} A_{\beta} \coloneqq
\{\xi < \alpha : \xi \in \bigcap \{A_{\beta} : \beta < \xi\} \}
= \bigcap_{\beta < \alpha} ([0,\beta] \cup A_\beta)
\]
\end{definition}
\begin{remark}+
\label{rem:diagiclosed}
Note that if $A$ is closed,
so is $[0,\alpha] \cup A$.
Since the intersection of arbitrarily many
closed sets is closed,
we get that the diagonal intersection
of closed sets is closed.
\end{remark}
\begin{lemma}
\label{lem:diagiclub}
Let $\kappa$ be a regular, uncountable cardinal.
@ -181,22 +190,23 @@ We have shown (assuming \AxC to choose contained clubs):
$\diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_{\beta}$ is closed in $\kappa$.
\end{claim}
\begin{subproof}
Let $\gamma < \kappa$ be such that $\left( \diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_{\beta} \right) \cap \gamma$
is unbounded in $\gamma$.
We aim to show that $\gamma \in \diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_{\beta}$.
Let $\beta_0 < \gamma$.
We need to see that $\gamma \in D_{\beta_0}$.
Cf.~\yaref{rem:diagiclosed}.
% Let $\gamma < \kappa$ be such that $\left( \diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_{\beta} \right) \cap \gamma$
% is unbounded in $\gamma$.
% We aim to show that $\gamma \in \diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_{\beta}$.
% Let $\beta_0 < \gamma$.
% We need to see that $\gamma \in D_{\beta_0}$.
For each $\beta_0 \le \beta' < \gamma$
there is some $\beta'' \in \diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_\beta$
such that $\beta' \le \beta'' < \gamma$,
since $\gamma = \sup((\diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_\beta) \cap \gamma)$.
In particular $\beta'' \in D_{\beta_0}$.
% For each $\beta_0 \le \beta' < \gamma$
% there is some $\beta'' \in \diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_\beta$
% such that $\beta' \le \beta'' < \gamma$,
% since $\gamma = \sup((\diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_\beta) \cap \gamma)$.
% In particular $\beta'' \in D_{\beta_0}$.
So $D_{\beta_0} \cap \gamma$
is unbounded in $\gamma$.
Since $D_{\beta_0}$ is closed
it follows that $\gamma \in D_{\beta_0}$.
% So $D_{\beta_0} \cap \gamma$
% is unbounded in $\gamma$.
% Since $D_{\beta_0}$ is closed
% it follows that $\gamma \in D_{\beta_0}$.
%As $\beta_0 < \gamma$ was arbitrary,
%this shows that $\gamma \in \diagi_{\beta < n} D_\beta$.
@ -270,9 +280,9 @@ We have shown (assuming \AxC to choose contained clubs):
\end{refproof}
\begin{remark}+
$\diagi_{\beta < \kappa} C_{\beta}$ actually
\emph{is} a club:
It suffices to show that $\diagi_{\beta < \kappa} C_\beta$ is closed.
This can be shown in the same way as for $\diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_\beta$.
\emph{is} a club,
since $\diagi_{\beta < \kappa} C_\beta$ is closed,
again cf.~\yaref{rem:diagiclosed}.
% Let $\lambda < \kappa$ be a limit ordinal.
% Suppose that $\lambda \not\in \diagi_{\beta < \kappa} D_\beta$.
% Then there exists $\alpha < \lambda$ such that
@ -288,6 +298,20 @@ We have shown (assuming \AxC to choose contained clubs):
iff $C \cap S \neq \emptyset$
for every club $C \subseteq \kappa$.
\end{definition}
\begin{remark}+[\url{https://mathoverflow.net/q/37503}]
Informally, club sets and stationary sets
can be viewed as large sets of a measure space
of measure $1$.
Clubs behave similarly to sets of measure $1$
and stationary sets are analogous to
sets of positive measure:
\begin{itemize}
\item Every club is stationary,
\item the intersection of two clubs is a club,
\item the intersection of a club and a stationary set is stationary,
\item there exist disjoint stationary sets.
\end{itemize}
\end{remark}
\begin{example}
\begin{itemize}
\item Every $D \subseteq \kappa$ which is club in $\kappa$

View file

@ -43,7 +43,6 @@ Recall that $F \subseteq \cP(\kappa)$ is a filter if
$X,Y \in F \implies X \cap Y \in F$,
$X \in F, X \subseteq Y \subseteq \kappa \implies Y \in F$
and $\emptyset \not\in F, \kappa \in F$.
\todo{Move this to the definition of filter?}
}{}
\begin{definition}
A filter $F$ is an \vocab{ultrafilter}
@ -104,11 +103,7 @@ one cofinality.
\begin{refproof}{thm:solovay}%
\gist{%
%\footnote{``This is one of the arguments where it is certainly
% worth it to look at it again''}
% TODO: Look at this again and think about it.
% TODO TODO TODO
\footnote{``This is one of the arguments where it is certainly worth it to look at it again.''}
We will only prove this for $\aleph_1$.
Fix $S \subseteq \aleph_1$ stationary.
@ -144,7 +139,7 @@ one cofinality.
\end{claim}
\begin{subproof}
Otherwise for all $n < \omega$,
there is a $\delta$ such that
there is a $\delta$ such that
$\{\alpha \in S^\ast : \gamma_n^{\alpha} > \delta\}$
is nonstationary.
Let $\delta_n$ be the least such $\delta$.
@ -196,20 +191,23 @@ one cofinality.
$\gamma_n^{\alpha} = \delta'$.
Write $\delta_i = \delta'$ and $T_i = T$.
\begin{claim}
\label{thm:solovay:p:c2}
Each $T_i$ is stationary
and if $i \neq j$, then $T_i \cap T_j = \emptyset$.
\footnote{maybe this should not be a claim}
\end{claim}
\begin{subproof}
The first part is true by construction.
Let $j < i$.
Then if $\alpha \in T_i$, $\alpha' \in T_j$,
we get $\gamma_n^{\alpha'} = \delta_j < \delta_i = \gamma_n^{\alpha}$
hence $\alpha \neq \alpha'$.
\end{subproof}
By construction, all the $T_i$ are stationary.
Since the $\delta_i$ are strictly increasing
and since $\gamma_n^{\alpha} = \delta_i$ for all $\alpha \in T_i$,
we have that the $T_i$ are disjoint.
% \begin{claim}
% \label{thm:solovay:p:c2}
% Each $T_i$ is stationary
% and if $i \neq j$, then $T_i \cap T_j = \emptyset$.
% \end{claim}
% \begin{subproof}
% The first part is true by construction.
% Let $j < i$.
% Then if $\alpha \in T_i$, $\alpha' \in T_j$,
% we get $\gamma_n^{\alpha'} = \delta_j < \delta_i = \gamma_n^{\alpha}$
% hence $\alpha \neq \alpha'$.
% \end{subproof}
Now let
\[
@ -232,8 +230,6 @@ one cofinality.
\item $\exists n < \omega.~\forall \delta < \omega_1: \{\alpha \in S^\ast : \gamma^{\alpha}_n > \delta\}$
stationary:
\begin{itemize}
% TODO THINK!
% TODO TODO TODO
\item Otherwise $\forall n < \omega.~\exists \delta.~\{\alpha \in S^\ast : \gamma^{\alpha}_n > \delta\} $ nonstationary.
\item $\delta_n\coloneqq $ least such $\delta$,
$C_n$ club s.t.~$C_n \cap \{\alpha \in S^\ast : \gamma^{\alpha}_n > \delta_n\} = \emptyset$.

View file

@ -1,9 +1,6 @@
\lecture{17}{2023-12-14}{Silver's Theorem}
We now want to prove \yaref{thm:silver}.
% More generally, if $\kappa$ is a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality
% such that $2^{\lambda} = \lambda^+$ for all $\lambda < \kappa$,
% then $2^{\kappa} = \kappa^+$.
\gist{%
\begin{remark}
@ -12,7 +9,7 @@ We now want to prove \yaref{thm:silver}.
\end{remark}
}{}
We will only proof
We will only prove
\gist{%
\yaref{thm:silver} in the special case that $\kappa = \aleph_{\omega_1}$
(see \yaref{thm:silver1}).
@ -153,6 +150,7 @@ We will only proof
Let $\beta < \omega_1$ be such that for all $Y \in A_2$
and for all $\alpha \in T$, $h_Y(\alpha) = \beta$.
% TODO WHY DOES THIS WORK?
Then $\overline{f}_Y(\alpha) < \aleph_\beta$
for all $Y \in A_2$ and $\alpha \in T$.

View file

@ -27,7 +27,6 @@
Since $2^{\lambda} < \kappa$,
\AxPow works.
The other axioms are trivial.
\todo{Exercise}
\end{proof}
\begin{corollary}
$\ZFC$ does not prove the existence of inaccessible
@ -40,7 +39,7 @@
\end{proof}
\begin{definition}[Ulam]
A cardinal $\kappa > \aleph_0$ is \vocab{measurable}
A cardinal $\kappa > \aleph_0$ is \vocab{measurable}
iff there is an ultrafilter $U$ on $\kappa$,
such that $U$ is not principal\gist{\footnote{%
i.e.~$\{\xi\} \not\in U$ for all $\xi < \kappa$%

View file

@ -79,6 +79,7 @@ and $\forall x \in y.~\phi$ abbreviates $\forall x.~x \in y \to \phi$.
A similar arguments yields \vocab{upwards absoluteness} for $\Sigma_1$-formulas
and \vocab{downwards absoluteness} for $\Pi_1$-formulas:
\begin{lemma}
\label{lem:pi1downardsabsolute}
Let $M$ be transitive.
Let $\phi(x_0,\ldots,x_n) \in \cL_\in$ and $a_0,\ldots,a_n \in M$.
Then

View file

@ -112,7 +112,7 @@ is well founded.
The formula $\forall x.~\forall y .~((\forall z \in x.~z \in y \land \forall z \in y.~z \in x) \to x = y)$
is $\Pi_1$, hence it is true in $M[g]$
by %TODO REF downward absolutenes.
by \yaref{lem:pi1downardsabsolute}.
\item \AxFund:
Again,
\[
@ -137,7 +137,7 @@ is well founded.
so $M[g] \models \text{``$\{x,y\}$ is the pair of $x$ and $y$''}$.
Hence $M[g] \models \AxPair$.
\item \AxUnion:
Similar to \AxPair.\gist{\todo{Exercise}}{}
Similar to \AxPair.
\end{itemize}
\end{proof}
@ -194,7 +194,6 @@ Still missing are
\[
p \Vdash^{\mathbb{P}}_M \phi(\tau_1,\ldots, \tau_k).
\]
\end{enumerate}
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}