some changes
Some checks failed
Build latex and deploy / checkout (push) Failing after 17m22s

This commit is contained in:
Josia Pietsch 2024-02-15 04:44:48 +01:00
parent 858e017a4a
commit f4626be14b
Signed by: josia
GPG key ID: E70B571D66986A2D
9 changed files with 77 additions and 15 deletions

View file

@ -1,4 +1,5 @@
\lecture{02}{2023-10-19}{Topology on $\R$} \lecture{02}{2023-10-19}{Topology on $\R$}
\gist{%
\begin{definition} \begin{definition}
A set $O \subseteq \R$ is called \vocab{open} in $\R$ iff it is the union A set $O \subseteq \R$ is called \vocab{open} in $\R$ iff it is the union
of a set of open intervals. of a set of open intervals.
@ -20,6 +21,7 @@
\begin{remark}+ \begin{remark}+
$\{O \subseteq \R\} \sim 2^{\aleph_0} < \cP(\R)$. $\{O \subseteq \R\} \sim 2^{\aleph_0} < \cP(\R)$.
\end{remark} \end{remark}
}{}
\begin{definition} \begin{definition}
We call $x \in \R$ We call $x \in \R$
@ -28,9 +30,11 @@
there is some $y \in A$, $y \in (a,b)$, $y \neq x$. there is some $y \in A$, $y \in (a,b)$, $y \neq x$.
We write \vocab{$A'$} for the set of all accumulation points of $A$. We write \vocab{$A'$} for the set of all accumulation points of $A$.
\end{definition} \end{definition}
\gist{%
\begin{example} \begin{example}
$\{\frac{1}{n+1} | n \in \N\}' = \{0\}$. $\{\frac{1}{n+1} | n \in \N\}' = \{0\}$.
\end{example} \end{example}
}{}
\begin{lemma} \begin{lemma}
\label{lem:closedaccumulation} \label{lem:closedaccumulation}
@ -38,9 +42,11 @@
\end{lemma} \end{lemma}
\begin{refproof}{lem:closedaccumulation} \begin{refproof}{lem:closedaccumulation}
``$\implies$'' ``$\implies$''
\gist{%
Let $A$ be closed. Suppose that $x \in A' \setminus A$. Let $A$ be closed. Suppose that $x \in A' \setminus A$.
Then there exists $(a,b) \ni x$ Then there exists $(a,b) \ni x$
disjoint from $A$. Hence $x \not\in A' \lightning$ disjoint from $A$. Hence $x \not\in A' \lightning$
}{trivial.}
``$\impliedby$'' ``$\impliedby$''
Suppose $A' \subseteq A$. Suppose $A' \subseteq A$.
@ -48,6 +54,7 @@
$A \subseteq \R$ is closed iff all Cauchy sequences $A \subseteq \R$ is closed iff all Cauchy sequences
in $A$ converge in $A$. in $A$ converge in $A$.
\end{claim} \end{claim}
\gist{%
\begin{subproof} \begin{subproof}
Let $A$ be closed and $\langle x_n : n \in \omega \rangle$ Let $A$ be closed and $\langle x_n : n \in \omega \rangle$
a Cauchy sequence in $A$. a Cauchy sequence in $A$.
@ -62,6 +69,7 @@
we may pick $x_n \in (x - \frac{1}{n+1}, x + \frac{1}{n+1}) \cap A$ we may pick $x_n \in (x - \frac{1}{n+1}, x + \frac{1}{n+1}) \cap A$
for all $n < \omega$. for all $n < \omega$.
\end{subproof} \end{subproof}
}{}
Now if $A' \subseteq A$ and $A$ were not closed, Now if $A' \subseteq A$ and $A$ were not closed,
there would be some Cauchy-sequence $(x_n)$ there would be some Cauchy-sequence $(x_n)$
@ -92,6 +100,7 @@ We want to prove two things:
Then $P \sim \R$. Then $P \sim \R$.
\end{lemma} \end{lemma}
\begin{proof} \begin{proof}
\gist{%
It suffices to find an injection $f\colon \R \hookrightarrow P$. It suffices to find an injection $f\colon \R \hookrightarrow P$.
We have $\underbrace{\{0,1\}^{\omega}}_{\text{infinite 0-1-sequences}} \sim \R$, We have $\underbrace{\{0,1\}^{\omega}}_{\text{infinite 0-1-sequences}} \sim \R$,
hence it suffices to construct $f\colon \{0,1\}^\omega\hookrightarrow P$. hence it suffices to construct $f\colon \{0,1\}^\omega\hookrightarrow P$.
@ -132,4 +141,5 @@ We want to prove two things:
and $f(t') \in [a_{t'\defon{n}}, b_{t'\defon{n}}]$ and $f(t') \in [a_{t'\defon{n}}, b_{t'\defon{n}}]$
which are disjoint. which are disjoint.
Thus $f(t) \neq f(t')$, i.e.~$f$ is injective. Thus $f(t) \neq f(t')$, i.e.~$f$ is injective.
}{Cantor scheme.}
\end{proof} \end{proof}

View file

@ -77,7 +77,7 @@ all condensation points are accumulation points.
\begin{subproof} \begin{subproof}
$P \neq \emptyset$: $\checkmark$ $P \neq \emptyset$: $\checkmark$
$P \subseteq P'$ (i.e. $P$ is closed): $P \subseteq P'$:
% \begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl} % \begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl}
% P &=& \{x \in A | \text{every open neighbourhood of $x$ is uncountable}\}\\ % P &=& \{x \in A | \text{every open neighbourhood of $x$ is uncountable}\}\\
% &\subseteq & \{x \in A | \text{every open neighbourhood of $x$ is at least countable}\} = P'. % &\subseteq & \{x \in A | \text{every open neighbourhood of $x$ is at least countable}\} = P'.
@ -97,7 +97,7 @@ all condensation points are accumulation points.
But then $(a,b) \cap A$ is at most countable But then $(a,b) \cap A$ is at most countable
contradicting $ x \in P$. contradicting $ x \in P$.
$P' \subseteq P$ : $P' \subseteq P$ (i.e.~$P$ is closed):
Let $x \in P'$. Let $x \in P'$.
Then for $a < x < b$ the set Then for $a < x < b$ the set
$(a,b) \cap P$ $(a,b) \cap P$

View file

@ -12,6 +12,7 @@ $\ZFC$ stands for
\item \textsc{Fraenkel}'s axioms, \item \textsc{Fraenkel}'s axioms,
\item the \yaref{ax:c}. \item the \yaref{ax:c}.
\end{itemize} \end{itemize}
\gist{
\begin{notation} \begin{notation}
We write $x \subseteq y$ as a shorthand We write $x \subseteq y$ as a shorthand
for $\forall z.~(z \in x \implies z \in y)$. for $\forall z.~(z \in x \implies z \in y)$.
@ -45,6 +46,7 @@ $\ZFC$ stands for
\forall u.~((u \in z) \iff (u \in x \land u \not\in y)). \forall u.~((u \in z) \iff (u \in x \land u \not\in y)).
\] \]
\end{notation} \end{notation}
}{Trivial, boring notation.}
$\ZFC$ consists of the following axioms: $\ZFC$ consists of the following axioms:
\begin{axiom}[\vocab{Extensionality}] \begin{axiom}[\vocab{Extensionality}]
\yalabel{Axiom of Extensionality}{(Ext)}{ax:ext} % (AoE) \yalabel{Axiom of Extensionality}{(Ext)}{ax:ext} % (AoE)
@ -148,13 +150,15 @@ $\ZFC$ consists of the following axioms:
\begin{axiomschema}[\vocab{Replacement} (Fraenkel)] \begin{axiomschema}[\vocab{Replacement} (Fraenkel)]
\yalabel{Axiom of Replacement}{(Rep)}{ax:rep} \yalabel{Axiom of Replacement}{(Rep)}{ax:rep}
Let $\phi$ be some $\cL_{\in }$ formula Let $\phi$ be some $\cL_{\in }$ formula
with free variables $x, y$.\todo{Allow more variables} with free variables $x, y$.
Then Then
\[ \begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{l}
\forall x \in a.~\exists !y \phi(x,y) \implies \exists b.~\forall x \in a.~\exists y \in b.~\phi(x,y). \forall v_1 \ldots \forall v_p.~\\
\left[\left( \forall x \exists! y.~\phi(x,y,\overline{v})\right) \to \forall a .~\exists b .~\forall y.~(y \in b \leftrightarrow \exists x (x \in a \land \phi(x,y, \overline{v}))\right]
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
%\forall x \in a.~\exists !y \phi(x,y) \implies \exists b.~\forall x \in a.~\exists y \in b.~\phi(x,y).
% \forall v_1 \ldots \forall v_p .~\forall x.~ \exists y'.~\forall y.~(y = y' \iff \phi(x)) % \forall v_1 \ldots \forall v_p .~\forall x.~ \exists y'.~\forall y.~(y = y' \iff \phi(x))
% \implies \forall a.~\exists b.~\forall y.~(y \in b \iff \exists x.~(x \in a \land \phi(x)) % \implies \forall a.~\exists b.~\forall y.~(y \in b \iff \exists x.~(x \in a \land \phi(x))
\]
\end{axiomschema} \end{axiomschema}
\begin{axiom}[\vocab{Choice}] \begin{axiom}[\vocab{Choice}]

View file

@ -23,6 +23,7 @@
\] \]
\end{definition} \end{definition}
\gist{%
\begin{definition} \begin{definition}
For sets $x, y$ we write For sets $x, y$ we write
$(x,y)$ for $\{\{x\}, \{x,y\}\}$. $(x,y)$ for $\{\{x\}, \{x,y\}\}$.
@ -130,7 +131,7 @@
(In other mathematical fields, this is sometimes (In other mathematical fields, this is sometimes
denoted as $f(a)$. We don't do that here.) denoted as $f(a)$. We don't do that here.)
\end{notation} \end{notation}
}{[Some boring definitions omitted.]}
\begin{definition} \begin{definition}
A binary relation $\le $ on a set $a$ A binary relation $\le $ on a set $a$
is a \vocab{partial order} is a \vocab{partial order}
@ -168,7 +169,6 @@
x \in b \land \forall y \in b.~y \le x. x \in b \land \forall y \in b.~y \le x.
\] \]
In a similar way we define \vocab[Minimal element]{minimal elements} In a similar way we define \vocab[Minimal element]{minimal elements}
and the \vocab{minimum} of $b$. and the \vocab{minimum} of $b$.
We say that $x $ is an \vocab{upper bound} We say that $x $ is an \vocab{upper bound}
@ -181,6 +181,7 @@
(This does not necessarily exist.) (This does not necessarily exist.)
Similarly $\text{\vocab{$\inf$}}(b)$ is defined. Similarly $\text{\vocab{$\inf$}}(b)$ is defined.
\end{definition} \end{definition}
\gist{
\begin{remark}+ \begin{remark}+
Note that in a partial order, Note that in a partial order,
a maximal element is not necessarily a maximum. a maximal element is not necessarily a maximum.
@ -200,6 +201,7 @@
We write $(a,\le_a) \cong (b, \le_b)$ We write $(a,\le_a) \cong (b, \le_b)$
if they are isomorphic. if they are isomorphic.
\end{definition} \end{definition}
}{}
\begin{definition} \begin{definition}
Let $(a,\le)$ be a partial order. Let $(a,\le)$ be a partial order.
Then $(a,\le)$ is Then $(a,\le)$ is

View file

@ -8,6 +8,7 @@
Then $a$ has a maximal element. Then $a$ has a maximal element.
\end{theorem} \end{theorem}
\begin{refproof}{thm:zorn} \begin{refproof}{thm:zorn}
\gist{%
Fix $(a, \le )$ as in the hypothesis. Fix $(a, \le )$ as in the hypothesis.
Let $A \coloneqq \{ \{(b,x) : x \in b\} : b \subseteq a, b \neq \emptyset\}$. Let $A \coloneqq \{ \{(b,x) : x \in b\} : b \subseteq a, b \neq \emptyset\}$.
Note that $A$ is a set (use separation on $\cP(\cP(a) \times \bigcup \cP(a))$). Note that $A$ is a set (use separation on $\cP(\cP(a) \times \bigcup \cP(a))$).
@ -65,6 +66,36 @@
Then $B = B_{u_0}^{\le^{\ast\ast}}$. Then $B = B_{u_0}^{\le^{\ast\ast}}$.
So $\le^{\ast\ast} \in W$, but now $u_0 \in b$. So $\le^{\ast\ast} \in W$, but now $u_0 \in b$.
So $b$ must have a maximum. So $b$ must have a maximum.
\todo{Why does this prove the lemma?}
}{
\begin{itemize}
\item $A \coloneqq \{\{(b,x) : x \in b\}, b \subseteq a, b \neq \emptyset\}$.
\item \AxC $\leadsto$ choice function on $A$,
$f\colon \cP(a) \setminus \{\emptyset\} \to a$, $f(b) \in b$.
\item $\le^\ast$ on $a$:
\begin{itemize}
\item $W \coloneqq \{\le' \text{wo on} b \subseteq a : \forall u,b \in b.~u \le' v \implies u \le v, B_u^{\le '} \neq \emptyset, u = f(B^{\le '}_u)\}$ where
\item $B_u^{\le'} = \{w \in a : w \text{ $\le $-upper bound of } \{v \in b : v <' u\} \}$.
\end{itemize}
\item $\le', \le '' \in W \implies \le' \substack{\subseteq\\\supseteq} \le''$:
\begin{itemize}
\item $(b, \le') \overset{g}{\cong} (c, \le'') (\defon{v})$.
\item $g = \id_b$:
\begin{itemize}
\item $u_0$ $\le'$ minimal with $g(u_0) \neq u_0$.
\item $\{w \in b : w <' u_0\} \overset{g \defon{\ldots}}{=} \{w \in c : w <'' g(u_0)\}$.
\item $B^{\le '}_{u_0} = B_{g(u_0)}^{\le ''} \neq \emptyset$,
so $u_0 = f(B^{\le '}_{u_0}) = f(B^{\le ''}_{g(u_0)}) = g(u_0) \lightning$
\end{itemize}
\end{itemize}
\item $\le^\ast \coloneqq \bigcup W$ is wo on $b \subseteq a$.
\item Suppose $b$ has no maximum. Then $B \cap b = \emptyset$.
\item $u_0 \coloneqq f(B)$, $\le^{\ast\ast} = \le^\ast \cup \{(u,u_0) | u \in b\} \cup \{(u_0,u_0)\}$.
\item $B = B_{u_0}^{\le^{\ast\ast}}$, so $\le^{\ast\ast} \in W$,
but $u_0 \in b \lightning$. ?
\end{itemize}
}
\end{refproof} \end{refproof}
\begin{remark} \begin{remark}
@ -82,6 +113,7 @@
Then $A$ contains a $\subseteq$-maximal element. Then $A$ contains a $\subseteq$-maximal element.
\end{corollary} \end{corollary}
\gist{%
\begin{remark}[Cultural enrichment] \begin{remark}[Cultural enrichment]
Other assertions which are equivalent Other assertions which are equivalent
to the \yaref{ax:c}: to the \yaref{ax:c}:
@ -96,12 +128,14 @@
\item Every set can be well-ordered.%\footnote{This is clearly false.} \item Every set can be well-ordered.%\footnote{This is clearly false.}
\end{itemize} \end{itemize}
\end{remark} \end{remark}
}{}
% \begin{remark} % \begin{remark}
% The axiom of choice is true. % The axiom of choice is true.
% \end{remark} % \end{remark}
\pagebreak \pagebreak
\subsection{The Ordinals} \subsection{The Ordinals}
\gist{
\begin{goal} \begin{goal}
We want to define nice representatives of the equivalence classes We want to define nice representatives of the equivalence classes
of well-orders. of well-orders.
@ -115,7 +149,7 @@ We can hence form the smallest inductive set
Note that $\omega$ exists, as it is a subset of the inductive Note that $\omega$ exists, as it is a subset of the inductive
set given by \AxInf. set given by \AxInf.
We call $\omega$ the set of \vocab{natural numbers}. We call $\omega$ the set of \vocab{natural numbers}.
}{}
\begin{notation} \begin{notation}
We write $0$ for $\emptyset$, We write $0$ for $\emptyset$,
and $y + 1$ for $y \cup \{y\}$. and $y + 1$ for $y \cup \{y\}$.
@ -147,16 +181,19 @@ We have the following principle of induction:
and for all $y, z \in x$, and for all $y, z \in x$,
we have that $y = z$, $y \in z$ or $y \ni z$. we have that $y = z$, $y \in z$ or $y \ni z$.
\end{definition} \end{definition}
\gist{
Clearly, the $\in$-relation is a well-order on an ordinal $x$. Clearly, the $\in$-relation is a well-order on an ordinal $x$.
\begin{remark} \begin{remark}
This definition is due to \textsc{John von Neumann}. This definition is due to \textsc{John von Neumann}.
\end{remark} \end{remark}
}{}
\begin{lemma} \begin{lemma}
Each natural number (i.e.~element of $\omega$) Each natural number (i.e.~element of $\omega$)
is an ordinal. is an ordinal.
\end{lemma} \end{lemma}
\begin{proof} \begin{proof}
\gist{
We use \yaref{lem:induction}. We use \yaref{lem:induction}.
Clearly $\emptyset$ is an ordinal. Clearly $\emptyset$ is an ordinal.
Now let $\alpha$ be an ordinal. Now let $\alpha$ be an ordinal.
@ -169,6 +206,7 @@ Clearly, the $\in$-relation is a well-order on an ordinal $x$.
since $\alpha$ is an ordinal. since $\alpha$ is an ordinal.
Suppose $x = \alpha$. Suppose $x = \alpha$.
Then either $y = x$ or $y \in \alpha = x$. Then either $y = x$ or $y \in \alpha = x$.
}{Induction}
\end{proof} \end{proof}
\begin{lemma} \begin{lemma}

View file

@ -20,6 +20,7 @@
\end{enumerate} \end{enumerate}
\end{lemma} \end{lemma}
\begin{refproof}{lem:7:ordinalfacts} \begin{refproof}{lem:7:ordinalfacts}
\gist{
We have already proved (a) before. We have already proved (a) before.
(b) Fix $x \in \alpha$. Then $x \subseteq \alpha$. (b) Fix $x \in \alpha$. Then $x \subseteq \alpha$.
@ -113,6 +114,7 @@
But this violates \AxFund, But this violates \AxFund,
as $\alpha_0 \in \beta_0 \in \alpha_0$. as $\alpha_0 \in \beta_0 \in \alpha_0$.
\end{subproof} \end{subproof}
}{Long and tedious, but not many ideas.}
\end{refproof} \end{refproof}
\begin{lemma} \begin{lemma}
@ -146,6 +148,7 @@ for example $\bigcup \omega = \omega$.
Otherwise $\alpha$ is called Otherwise $\alpha$ is called
a \vocab[Ordinal!limit]{limit ordinal}. a \vocab[Ordinal!limit]{limit ordinal}.
\end{definition} \end{definition}
\gist{
\begin{observe} \begin{observe}
Note that $\alpha$ is a limit ordinal iff for all Note that $\alpha$ is a limit ordinal iff for all
$\beta \in \alpha$, $\beta + 1 \in \alpha$: $\beta \in \alpha$, $\beta + 1 \in \alpha$:
@ -158,7 +161,8 @@ for example $\bigcup \omega = \omega$.
then by definition there is some $\beta \in \alpha$, then by definition there is some $\beta \in \alpha$,
with $\beta + 1 = \alpha$, so $\beta + 1 \not\in \alpha$. with $\beta + 1 = \alpha$, so $\beta + 1 \not\in \alpha$.
\end{observe} \end{observe}
}{}
\gist{
\begin{notation} \begin{notation}
If $\alpha, \beta$ are ordinals, If $\alpha, \beta$ are ordinals,
we write $\alpha < \beta$ for $\alpha \in \beta$ we write $\alpha < \beta$ for $\alpha \in \beta$
@ -185,3 +189,4 @@ for example $\bigcup \omega = \omega$.
\item $\omega +1 = \omega \cup \{\omega\} , \omega + 2, \ldots$, \item $\omega +1 = \omega \cup \{\omega\} , \omega + 2, \ldots$,
\end{itemize} \end{itemize}
\end{example} \end{example}
}{}

View file

@ -1,6 +1,7 @@
\lecture{08}{2023-11-13}{Induction and recursion} \lecture{08}{2023-11-13}{Induction and recursion}
\subsection{Classes} \subsection{Classes}
\gist{
It is often very handy to work in a class theory rather than It is often very handy to work in a class theory rather than
in set theory. in set theory.
@ -11,10 +12,11 @@ sets (denoted by lower case letters)
and classes (denoted by capital letters), and classes (denoted by capital letters),
as well as one binary relation symbol $\in$ as well as one binary relation symbol $\in$
for membership. for membership.
}{}
\vocab{Bernays-Gödel class theory} (\vocab{BG}) \vocab{Bernays-Gödel class theory} (\vocab{BG})
has the following axioms: has the following axioms:
\gist{
\begin{axiom}[Extensionality] \begin{axiom}[Extensionality]
\yalabel{Axiom of Extensionality}{(Ext)}{ax:bg:ext} \yalabel{Axiom of Extensionality}{(Ext)}{ax:bg:ext}
\[ \[
@ -54,6 +56,7 @@ has the following axioms:
\exists x .~(\emptyset \in x \land \left( \forall y \in x .~y \cup \{y\} \in x \right)). \exists x .~(\emptyset \in x \land \left( \forall y \in x .~y \cup \{y\} \in x \right)).
\] \]
\end{axiom} \end{axiom}
}{\AxExt, \AxFund, \AxPair, \AxUnion, \AxPow, \AxInf as from $\ZF$.}
Together with the following axioms for classes: Together with the following axioms for classes:

View file

@ -298,7 +298,7 @@ We have shown (assuming \AxC to choose contained clubs):
and $S_1 \coloneqq \{\xi < \kappa : \cf(\xi) = \omega_1\}$. and $S_1 \coloneqq \{\xi < \kappa : \cf(\xi) = \omega_1\}$.
Clearly these are disjoint. Clearly these are disjoint.
They are both stationary: They are both stationary:
Let $c \subseteq \kappa$ be a club. Let $C \subseteq \kappa$ be a club.
Let $(\xi_i : i \le \omega_1)$ Let $(\xi_i : i \le \omega_1)$
be defined as follows: be defined as follows:
$\xi_0 \coloneqq \min C$, $\xi_0 \coloneqq \min C$,

View file

@ -252,7 +252,7 @@ We will only proof
\item $\forall Y \in A$ define $h_Y\colon S^\ast \to \omega_1, \alpha \mapsto \min \{\beta < \alpha : \overline{f}_Y(\alpha) < \aleph_\beta\}$. \item $\forall Y \in A$ define $h_Y\colon S^\ast \to \omega_1, \alpha \mapsto \min \{\beta < \alpha : \overline{f}_Y(\alpha) < \aleph_\beta\}$.
\item Apply \yaref{thm:fodor} to $h_Y, S^\ast$ to get $T_Y \subseteq S^\ast$ stationary with $h_Y\defon{T_Y}$ constant. \item Apply \yaref{thm:fodor} to $h_Y, S^\ast$ to get $T_Y \subseteq S^\ast$ stationary with $h_Y\defon{T_Y}$ constant.
\item $\exists T.~|\underbrace{\{Y \in A_S : T_Y = T\}}_{A_{S,T}}| = \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}$. \item $\exists T.~|\underbrace{\{Y \in A_S : T_Y = T\}}_{A_{S,T}}| = \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}$.
\item Let $\{\beta\} = g_Y''T$, i.e.~$\overline{f}_Y(\alpha) < \aleph_{\beta}$ for $Y\in A_{S,T}, \alpha \in T$. \item Let $\{\beta\} = h_Y''T$, i.e.~$\overline{f}_Y(\alpha) < \aleph_{\beta}$ for $Y\in A_{S,T}, \alpha \in T$.
\item $\leftindex^T \aleph_\beta \le 2^{\aleph_\beta \cdot \aleph_1} = \aleph_{\beta+1} \aleph_2 < \aleph_{ \omega_1}$. \item $\leftindex^T \aleph_\beta \le 2^{\aleph_\beta \cdot \aleph_1} = \aleph_{\beta+1} \aleph_2 < \aleph_{ \omega_1}$.
\item $\exists \tilde{f}\colon T \to \aleph_\beta .~ |\underbrace{\{Y \in A_{S,T} : \overline{f}_Y\defon{T} = \tilde{f}\} }_{A_{S,T,\tilde{f}}}| = \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}$. \item $\exists \tilde{f}\colon T \to \aleph_\beta .~ |\underbrace{\{Y \in A_{S,T} : \overline{f}_Y\defon{T} = \tilde{f}\} }_{A_{S,T,\tilde{f}}}| = \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}$.
\item $Y,Y' \in A_{S,T,\tilde{f}} \implies \forall \alpha \in T.~f_Y(\alpha) = f_{Y'}\left( \alpha \right) \overset{T \text{ unbounded}}{\implies} Y = Y'$ \item $Y,Y' \in A_{S,T,\tilde{f}} \implies \forall \alpha \in T.~f_Y(\alpha) = f_{Y'}\left( \alpha \right) \overset{T \text{ unbounded}}{\implies} Y = Y'$
@ -270,7 +270,7 @@ We will only proof
\item $P \coloneqq \{Y \subseteq \aleph_{ \omega_1} : \exists i < \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}.~Y \le X_i\}$ \item $P \coloneqq \{Y \subseteq \aleph_{ \omega_1} : \exists i < \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}.~Y \le X_i\}$
\end{itemize} \end{itemize}
\item $|P| \overset{\text{in fact } =}{\le} \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1} \aleph_{ \omega_1} = \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}$ by (3). \item $|P| \overset{\text{in fact } =}{\le} \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1} \aleph_{ \omega_1} = \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}$ by (3).
\item $X \in \cP(\aleph_{ \omega_1}) \setminus M \implies \forall i < \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}.~X_i \le X$ \item $X \in \cP(\aleph_{ \omega_1}) \setminus P \implies \forall i < \aleph_{ \omega_1 + 1}.~X_i \le X$
$\lightning$ (3). $\lightning$ (3).
Thus $P = \cP(\aleph_{ \omega_1})$. Thus $P = \cP(\aleph_{ \omega_1})$.
\end{itemize} \end{itemize}