240 lines
6.7 KiB
TeX
240 lines
6.7 KiB
TeX
|
\lecture{08}{2023-11-13}{Induction and recursion}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\subsection{Classes}
|
||
|
It is often very handy to work in a class theory rather than
|
||
|
in set theory.
|
||
|
|
||
|
To formulate a class theory,
|
||
|
we start out with a first order language
|
||
|
with two types of variables,
|
||
|
sets (denoted by lower case letters)
|
||
|
and classes (denoted by capital letters),
|
||
|
as well as one binary relation symbol $\in$
|
||
|
for membership.
|
||
|
|
||
|
\vocab{Bernays-Gödel class theory} (\vocab{BG})
|
||
|
has the following axioms:
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}[Extensionality]
|
||
|
\yalabel{Axiom of Extensionality}{(Ext)}{ax:bg:ext}
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\forall x, y. \left( x = y \iff \left( \forall z.~(z \in x \iff z \in y \right) \right).
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}[Foundation]
|
||
|
\yalabel{Axiom of Foundation}{(Fund)}{ax:bg:fund}
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\forall x .(x \neq \emptyset \implies \exists y \in x . y \cap x = \emptyset).
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}[Pairing]
|
||
|
\yalabel{Axiom of Pairing}{(Pair)}{ax:bg:pair}
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\forall x \forall y \exists z . z = \{x,y\}.
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}[Union]
|
||
|
\yalabel{Axiom of Union}{(Union)}{ax:bg:union}
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\forall x \exists y .~ y = \bigcup x.
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}[Power]
|
||
|
\yalabel{Powerset Axiom}{(Pow)}{ax:bg:pow}
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\forall x \exists y .~ y = \cP(x).
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}[Infinity]
|
||
|
\yalabel{Axiom of Infinity}{(Infinity)}{ax:bg:inf}
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\exists x . ~(\emptyset \in x \land \left( \forall y \in x .~y \cup \{y\} \in x \right)).
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
|
||
|
Together with the following axioms for classes:
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}[Extensionality for classes]
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\forall X \forall Y \left( \forall x(x \in X \iff y \in X) \implies X = Y).
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}
|
||
|
Every set is a class:
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\forall x \exists X. x = X.
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}
|
||
|
Every element of a class is a set:
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\forall X \exists Y.~(X \in Y \to \exists x.~x = X).
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}[Replacement]
|
||
|
\yalabel{Axiom of Replacement}{(Rep)}{ax:bg:rep}
|
||
|
|
||
|
If $F$ is a function and inf $a $ is a set,
|
||
|
then $F"a$ is a set.
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
Here a \vocab[Class function]{(class) function} is a class
|
||
|
consisting of pairs $(x,y)$,
|
||
|
such that for every $x$ there is at most one $y$
|
||
|
with $(x,y) \in F$.
|
||
|
Furthermore $F"a \coloneqq \{y : \exists x \in a .~(x,y) \in F\}$.
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{remark}
|
||
|
Note that we didn't need to use an axiom schema,
|
||
|
\yarefs{ax:bg:rep} is a single axiom.
|
||
|
\end{remark}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{axiom}[Comprehension]
|
||
|
\yalabel{Axiom of Comprehension}{(Comp)}{ax:bg:comp}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\[
|
||
|
\forall X_1 \ldots \forall X_k .~\exists Y ( \forall x .~x \in Y \iff \phi(x,X_1,\ldots, X_k))
|
||
|
\]
|
||
|
where $\phi(x, X_1, \ldots, X_k)$
|
||
|
is a formula which contains exactly $X_1, \ldots, X_k, x$
|
||
|
as free variables,
|
||
|
and $\phi$ does not have quantifiers
|
||
|
ranging over classes.%
|
||
|
\footnote{If one removes the restriction regarding
|
||
|
quantifiers another theory, called
|
||
|
\vocab{Morse-Kelly} set theory, is obtained.}
|
||
|
\end{axiom}
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
\todo{notation: $\emptyset, \cap$}
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
\subsection{Induction and Recursion}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{definition}
|
||
|
A binary relation $R$ on a set $X$,
|
||
|
i.e.~$R \subseteq X \times X$,
|
||
|
is called \vocab{well-founded}
|
||
|
iff for all $\emptyset \neq Y \subseteq X$
|
||
|
there is some $x \in Y$
|
||
|
such that for no $y \in Y. (y,x) \in R$.
|
||
|
\end{definition}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{example}
|
||
|
\begin{enumerate}[(a)]
|
||
|
\item $(\N, <)$ is well-founded.
|
||
|
\item Let $M$ be a set,
|
||
|
and let $\in\defon{M} \coloneqq \{(x,y) : x,y \in M \land x \in y\}$.
|
||
|
Fund is equivalent to saying that
|
||
|
this is a well-founded relation for every $M$.
|
||
|
\end{enumerate}
|
||
|
\end{example}
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{lemma}
|
||
|
\label{lem:fundseq}
|
||
|
In $\ZFC - \Fund$,
|
||
|
the following are equivalent:
|
||
|
\begin{itemize}
|
||
|
\item \Fund,
|
||
|
\item There is no sequence $\langle x_n : n < \omega \rangle$
|
||
|
such that $x_{n+1} \in x_n$ for all $n < \omega$.
|
||
|
\end{itemize}
|
||
|
\end{lemma}
|
||
|
\begin{proof}
|
||
|
Suppose such sequence exists.
|
||
|
Then $\{x_n : n < \omega\}$
|
||
|
(this exists as by definition sequence of the $x_n$ is a function
|
||
|
and this set is the range of that function)
|
||
|
violates \Fund.
|
||
|
|
||
|
For the other direction let $M \neq \emptyset$ be some set.
|
||
|
Suppose that \Fund does not hold for $M$.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Using \Choice,
|
||
|
we construct an infinite sequence $x_0 \ni x_1 \ni x_2 \ni \ldots$
|
||
|
of elements of $M$.
|
||
|
|
||
|
More formally,
|
||
|
for each $x \in M$
|
||
|
let $A_x \coloneqq \{y \in M: y \in x\}$.
|
||
|
Suppose that $A_x \neq \emptyset$ for all $x \in M$.
|
||
|
Using \AxC
|
||
|
we get a function for $\langle A_x : x \in M \rangle$,%
|
||
|
\footnote{Actually we only need the axiom of dependent choice,
|
||
|
a weaker form of the axiom of choice.
|
||
|
We'll discuss this later.% TODO REF
|
||
|
}
|
||
|
i.e.~a function $f\colon M \to M$
|
||
|
such that $f(x) \in A_x$ for $x \in M$.
|
||
|
Now fix $x \in M$.
|
||
|
We want to produce
|
||
|
a function
|
||
|
$g\colon \omega \to M$
|
||
|
such that
|
||
|
\begin{itemize}
|
||
|
\item $g(0) = x$,
|
||
|
\item $g(n+1) = f(g(n)) \in A_{g(n)}$.
|
||
|
\end{itemize}
|
||
|
|
||
|
Let
|
||
|
\begin{IEEEeqnarray*}{rCl}
|
||
|
G &=& \{\overline{g} : \exists n \in \omega . \\
|
||
|
&&~ ~\overline{g} \text{ is a function with domain $n$ and range $\subseteq M$, such that}\\
|
||
|
&&~ ~\overline{g}(0) = x \land \forall m \in \omega.~(m+1 \in \dom(\overline{g}) \implies \overline{g}(m+1) = f(\overline{g}(m)))\}.
|
||
|
\end{IEEEeqnarray*}
|
||
|
$G$ exists as it can be obtained by \AxSep
|
||
|
from ${}^{< \omega}M$.
|
||
|
By induction,
|
||
|
for every $n \in \omega$,
|
||
|
there is a $\overline{g} \in G$
|
||
|
with $\dom(\overline{g}) \in n+1$:
|
||
|
This holds for $n = 0$,
|
||
|
as $\{(0,x)\} \in G$.
|
||
|
If $\overline{g} \in G$ with $\dom(\overline{g}) = n+ 1$,
|
||
|
then $\overline{g} \cup \{(n+1, f(\overline{g}(n)))\} \in G$.
|
||
|
Also by induction,
|
||
|
for every $n \in \omega$,
|
||
|
there is a \emph{unique}
|
||
|
$\overline{g}$ with $\dom(\overline{g}) = n+1$.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Now let $g = \bigcup \overline{G}$.
|
||
|
Also let $g(0) = x$ and $g(n+1) = f(g(n))$
|
||
|
for all $n \in \omega$.
|
||
|
\end{proof}
|
||
|
|
||
|
\begin{lemma}[Dependent Choice]
|
||
|
Suppose that $M \neq \emptyset$
|
||
|
and $R$ is a binary relation on $M$
|
||
|
such that for all $x \in M$,
|
||
|
$A_x \coloneqq \{y \in M : (y,x) \in R\}$
|
||
|
is not empty.
|
||
|
|
||
|
Then for every $x \in M$ there exists a function
|
||
|
$g\colon \omega \to M$
|
||
|
such that $g(0) = x$
|
||
|
and $g(n+1) \in A_{g(n)}$
|
||
|
for all $n < \omega$.
|
||
|
\end{lemma}
|
||
|
\begin{proof}
|
||
|
We showed a special case of this in the proof of
|
||
|
\yaref{lem:fundseq}.
|
||
|
\end{proof}
|
||
|
\begin{remark}
|
||
|
In $\ZF$ this is a weaker form of \Choice.
|
||
|
\end{remark}
|
||
|
|
||
|
The construction of $g$ in the previous proof was a special case of
|
||
|
a construction on the proof of the recursion theorem: % TODO REF
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
|
||
|
|